Philosophy Explained
My progress participating in online philosophy courses from the Oxford University Department for Continuing Education
Tuesday, May 23, 2017
Tuesday, October 22, 2013
Online learning and the future of universities in the digital age
I am helping to organise a talk in Edinburgh for Oxford alumni and anyone else who is interested in the topic:
Details:
Details:
Friday 22nd November 2013, at The Royal Scots Club
A talk by Melissa Highton, Director of Academic IT and Head of Learning Technologies at Oxford University
Venue: The Royal Scots Club, 29 - 31 Abercromby Place, Edinburgh , EH3 6QE
Time: 6-8pm
Please let me know if you are interested in attending.
Sunday, August 11, 2013
Update
Apologies for the radio silence. Work got in the way of updating the blog, but I did successfully complete the course and received a credit for my final assignment:
Non-cognitivists believe
that when we act morally we must act to satisfy a desire of our own. Can such
an action be truly moral?
Non-cognitivists argue that there are no such
things as moral ‘properties’ or moral ‘facts’; moral statements do not have
truth conditions that we can establish through objective processes, all
statements of moral value involve subjective attitudes or desires. Non-cognitivists
therefore believe that when
people make moral statements they do not express states of mind which are
‘cognitive’ in the way that beliefs are, instead they express ‘non-cognitive’
attitudes. For many philosophers,
this view seems counter-intuitive, how can morality be based on what we subjectively
‘want’ rather than what we objectively ‘should do’?
As an early proponent of a form of moral non-cognitivism,
Hume argued that moral distinctions are not derived from reason. Hume divided the
processes of the mind into two distinct (and complementary) categories - passions
and reason; “Morals excite passions, and produce or prevent actions. Reason of
itself is utterly impotent in this particular. The rules of morality,
therefore, are not conclusions of our reason.”1
Other forms of non-cognitivism also hold that
when we act morally we must act to satisfy a desire. For example, emotivism is
the theory that a judgment
that some action is right is based on subjective approval of that action.
An analogy which supports the non-cognitivist
approach is that of mechanical robot. A robot can be programmed to have highly
advanced powers of reason - it’s CPU could perform millions of calculations per
second - but it cannot be ‘passionate’ in the way that a human can, it cannot
desire something to be the case. Robots cannot be moral agents. To reason is to
follow rules, but morality answers the question ‘which rules should we follow?’
A non-cognitivist argues that it is our passions that are the source of those
moral rules.
There are a number of objections to
non-cognitivist moral theories. Amoralists might argue that non-cognitivism
cannot be correct since there are many examples where we accept moral judgments
as being correct without being motivated to do what they recommend. They would therefore
reject emotivism on the basis that it does not account for the nature of moral
truth in real-world situations.
Another rejection of non-cognitivism is derived
from the altruistic nature of morality. If we accept that humans are
essentially selfish, how can this be a basis for a moral framework? Moral
behaviour, some argue, is that type of behaviour which suppresses selfish
motives and promotes altruistic behaviour. Emotivism is therefore rejected by
those who believe that it cannot account for the altruistic nature of moral
behaviour.
However, Darwinian evolutionary biology can provide
a defence of altruism based on non-cognitivist lines. Darwin argued that self-sacrificial behavior,
though disadvantageous for the individual, might still be beneficial at the
group level: “a tribe including many members who...were always ready to give
aid to each other and sacrifice themselves for the common good, would be
victorious over most other tribes; and this would be natural selection.”2 In
this sense we can argue that
humans may desire to act in a non-selfish way. Further, we can defend some actions
as moral without selfishly desiring them if, at an underlying genetic level, it
is in our interests to act in such a way. In this sense morality could be based
on instinctive or sub-conscious behaviour that creates desire or approbation in
us, whilst not based on a cognitive process.
Deontologists reject non-cognitivism as they
believe that there are moral truths that are based on moral rules. For example,
Kant argued that morality is founded on categorical imperatives which in turn
are derived from our human rationality. Kant entirely rejects a non-cognitivist
account of morality based on desires: “To preserve one’s life is a duty, and
besides everyone has an immediate inclination to do so. But on this account the
often anxious care that most people take of it still has no inner worth and
their maxim has no moral content.”3
I believe that a non-cognitivist approach is
more likely to explain moral values than a cognitivist one. I agree with Hume
that we cannot derive ‘ought’ from ‘is’. No set of premises consisting entirely of non-moral
descriptive statements is sufficient to entail a moral conclusion. GE Moore also argues in a similar vein that
where moral issues are ‘open questions’, their truth remains indefinable and
their normative value is not something that can be established through a
cognitivist process. I agree with Moore
that any attempt to solve the problems of morality cognitively is inherently problematic.
References
1 David Hume,
Treatise of Human Nature (1737), Book III
2 Charles Darwin, The Descent of
Man (1871), p166
3
Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), trans Mary J.
Gregor
Thursday, May 30, 2013
Darwin and morality
I'm aware there has been quite a bit of research and debate about how it is that humans and other animals have developed a propensity to altruism. I think this is tackled to some extent in The Selfish Gene and Dawkins' subsequent books. I do have a copy somewhere so if I get the chance I'll dig it out.
If the tribe is successful then it is likely that an individual's genes will be propagated, since presumably there was a lot of shared family history within each tribe (maybe that's what you were getting at?).
It is amazing how Darwin's work so accurately corresponds with what we now know about DNA. There was a fascinating TV programme about Alfred Russell Wallace a few weeks ago (hosted by Bill Bailey) which pointed out how unfair it is that he is almost forgotten whereas Darwin is given all of the credit. It does seem that evolution was an idea waiting to be discovered, I find it quite bizarre - not to say a little scary - that there are so many people (particularly in the US) who claim not to believe in evolution.
If the tribe is successful then it is likely that an individual's genes will be propagated, since presumably there was a lot of shared family history within each tribe (maybe that's what you were getting at?).
It is amazing how Darwin's work so accurately corresponds with what we now know about DNA. There was a fascinating TV programme about Alfred Russell Wallace a few weeks ago (hosted by Bill Bailey) which pointed out how unfair it is that he is almost forgotten whereas Darwin is given all of the credit. It does seem that evolution was an idea waiting to be discovered, I find it quite bizarre - not to say a little scary - that there are so many people (particularly in the US) who claim not to believe in evolution.
Tuesday, May 28, 2013
Why are we moral?
I would like propose that morality is a human attribute that has evolved through the process of natural selection and survival of the fittest. To quote from Darwin's 'Descent of Man':
"When two tribes of primeval man, living in the same country, came into competition, if the one tribe included…a greater number of courageous, sympathetic, and faithful members, who were always ready to warn each other of danger, to aid and defend each other, this tribe would without doubt succeed best and conquer the other….A tribe possessing the above qualities in a high degree would spread and be victorious over other tribes; but in the course of time it would, judging from all past history, be in its turn overcome by some other and still more highly endowed tribe. Thus the social and moral qualities would tend slowly to advance and be diffused throughout the world."
"When two tribes of primeval man, living in the same country, came into competition, if the one tribe included…a greater number of courageous, sympathetic, and faithful members, who were always ready to warn each other of danger, to aid and defend each other, this tribe would without doubt succeed best and conquer the other….A tribe possessing the above qualities in a high degree would spread and be victorious over other tribes; but in the course of time it would, judging from all past history, be in its turn overcome by some other and still more highly endowed tribe. Thus the social and moral qualities would tend slowly to advance and be diffused throughout the world."
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)